1.) The principle intus apparens is used to prove the immateriality of intellect. In speaking of it we will take two things as self-evident:
a.) Sense powers are passive physical cognitive powers.
b.) Human intellects are passive cognitive powers that are not self-evidently physical. One has to prove the case one way or another.
In this present argument, we postulate that the intellect is a form of a body (though we think, in fact, that it is provable.) The postulate is uncontroversial to those who think intellect is physical, so it does not seem any presumptive benefit to those of us who think that we can use it to prove the intellect is not physical.
2.) The principle intus apparens is
A passive cognitive faculty cannot have in its nature the form that it knows primo and per se.
“The form” in question is any form, whether existing in esse naturale and in esse intentionale. It is, however, both uncontroversial and evident from the terms that the nature of a passive faculty cannot have the form it knows in esse intentionale, since if it did it would not be passive to a form that makes it know, which is precisely what being a passive cognitive power consists in. We therefore leave that claim aside and focus only on why the nature of the passive cognitive faculty lacks the form it knows in any way, including in esse naturale.
3.) There are many objections to this claim which commentators have, for centuries, been taking as almost laughingly self-evident:
a.) Eyes see colors and have colors.
b.) Eyes see magnitudes and have magnitude.
c.) The organs we use to feel temperature have a temperature.
One can spin out objections like this ad infinitum, making it seem completely nuts to claim that passive cognitive powers have to lack the form they perceive in any way, including in esse naturale.
4a.) All the objections fail due to one evident universal principle, which we’ll first apply to exterior sense powers and next to interior sense powers. First, the exterior sense powers are passive per se to bodies exterior to the sense organ. It’s evident, however, that nothing exterior to a sense organ is interior to it. When we say, for example in (3a), that eyes see colors, we mean they see them precisely in the way appropriate to a passive, physical power that detects things exterior to itself. My eyes, for example, don’t see the black of my own pupils, the brown of my own irises, the white of my own sclera, but only, e.g. the black charcoal marks in a drawing of my pupil, the pixelated brown irises on my drivers license, or things like this that are exterior to the organ and capable of acting on it through light in the medium.
4b.) This is also true about interior sense powers, e.g. those that feel pain. The pain seems to be damage to a nerve relayed to a brain, which the brain treats as exterior to itself. The brain itself, interestingly, does not have pain receptors, and it cannot, per the account just given in keeping with the principle intus apparens. The only difference between the interior and exterior powers is between that the latter are a whole acting exteriorly on another whole while the former are a part acting exteriorly to on another part.
5.) There are also particular reasons for why the above objections fail. (b) fails to realize that the principle intus apparens applies to what the power knows primo and per se, and no common sensible (like magnitude) is known primo and per se, but only through the proper sensibles. We would say something similar to one who tried to say that the principle intus apparens proves that if intellects know being, then they can’t exist, as we’ll prove below that they don’t know being in all its latitude primo and per se. (c) fails from too loose and general account of the temperatures that touch detects, which are in a range between high temperatures that can harm us and low temperatures that can harm us, and dropping or raising the temperature of the organ itself (as happens in fevers) impedes its ability to correctly detect what is in this range. So far from disproving the principle, it presupposes it.
6.) Per (1b.) the intellect is a passive power. Aristotle also gave a proof for this, sc. the human intellect is passive because it sometimes knows and sometimes does not. The intellect also knows physical substances primo and per se since, given the postulate in (1), it knows everything it knows as the form of a body, but it clearly knows that physical things are substances, i.e. that they exist of themselves, are objective, and have features essential to them as physical, which are the only sorts of features that form universal laws. Notice that other physical, interior senses (like the estimative sense, common sense, etc) do not perceive substance primo and per se any more than the individual proper senses.
7.) Therefore, per (2) the human intellect in esse naturale is neither a physical substance nor is it composed of physical substances, and no exterior or interior sense power is such.
8.) The proof for the immateriality of the intellect presupposes that the intellect is a form united to a body, as this was a necessary postulate in proving that it physical substances are what it knew primo and per se. So even if the immateriality of the intellect is understood as involving some sort of substance dualism – sapiens non curat de nominibus – this “dualism” itself presupposes the unity of the intellect and physical organs in a single substance.
9.) This refutes Pasnau’s charge that Aquinas commits what he calls a content fallacy when he supposedly illicitly infers from what Pasnau calls internal to intentional characteristic of thought. Aquinas does this whenever the principle intus apparens allows him to, as this principle is explained in (2.)